Other Sellers on Amazon
Added
Not added
$72.48
+ FREE Delivery
+ FREE Delivery
Sold by: Amazon US
Sold by: Amazon US
Delivery rates and Return policy
Only 4 left in stock.
International Product from outside Australia Delivery rates and Return policy

Download the free Kindle app and start reading Kindle books instantly on your smartphone, tablet or computer—no Kindle device required.
Read instantly on your browser with Kindle for Web.
Using your mobile phone camera, scan the code below and download the Kindle app.
Follow the author
Something went wrong. Please try your request again later.
OK
Justinian's "Institutes" Paperback – 18 June 1987
by
Justinian
(Author)
{"desktop_buybox_group_1":[{"displayPrice":"$72.61","priceAmount":72.61,"currencySymbol":"$","integerValue":"72","decimalSeparator":".","fractionalValue":"61","symbolPosition":"left","hasSpace":false,"showFractionalPartIfEmpty":true,"offerListingId":"R7CGfhvEeLeWbEoNYkQRVifUKYPgw1a44jg1LnAFRD3pjAdgs%2F4EWFzvrpTR%2FJyaKpBYBa1xjgt7q07nZ%2FfDbv8n48%2BjuDx5y7brO0vloySAnUaWAArx2tZRHRoh7uvyubqAl57O9oswdDpQRlr7w9%2Fc1ayukEtT","locale":"en-AU","buyingOptionType":"NEW","aapiBuyingOptionIndex":0}]}
Purchase options and add-ons
- ISBN-100801494001
- ISBN-13978-0801494000
- Edition1st
- PublisherCornell University Press
- Publication date18 June 1987
- LanguageEnglish
- Dimensions15.24 x 1.12 x 22.86 cm
- Print length162 pages
Frequently bought together

This item: Justinian's "Institutes"
$72.61$72.61
Available to ship in 1-2 days
$79.87$79.87
Get it 18 - 26 Apr
Usually dispatched within 5 to 6 days
$148.26$148.26
Available to ship in 1-2 days
Total Price:
To see our price, add these items to your cart.
Try again!
Added to Cart
Some of these items dispatch sooner than the others.
Choose items to buy together.
Customers who viewed this item also viewed
Page 1 of 1 Start againPage 1 of 1
Product details
- Publisher : Cornell University Press; 1st edition (18 June 1987)
- Language : English
- Paperback : 162 pages
- ISBN-10 : 0801494001
- ISBN-13 : 978-0801494000
- Dimensions : 15.24 x 1.12 x 22.86 cm
- Best Sellers Rank: 176,927 in Books (See Top 100 in Books)
- 30 in Military Law (Books)
- 54 in Government Textbooks
- 60 in Political Reference
- Customer Reviews:
About the author
Follow authors to get new release updates, plus improved recommendations.

Discover more of the author’s books, see similar authors, read author blogs, and more
Customer reviews
4.8 out of 5 stars
4.8 out of 5
7 global ratings
How are ratings calculated?
To calculate the overall star rating and percentage breakdown by star, we don’t use a simple average. Instead, our system considers things like how recent a review is and if the reviewer bought the item on Amazon. It also analyses reviews to verify trustworthiness.
Top reviews from other countries

Paul Marks
4.0 out of 5 stars
The late Roman way of looking at law - that has had so much influence on the modern world.
Reviewed in the United Kingdom on 31 January 2013Verified Purchase
It should be made clear at the start that this is not (as commonally supposed) a "code" of law. By the time of Justinian Roman law had become a vast tidal wave of orders-commands (covering every aspect of life) that could not really be put into a code form.
This book is the late Roman way of looking at civil law - the rules of property, of inheritance and so on. It takes it for granted that the Emperor can change any law (that the will of the ruler trumps natural law - the exact opposite of how a scholastic in the Middle Ages would see the matter), but the work also assumes that there is a science (in the old sense of a body of knowledge - and way of reasoning) involved in law - that one can not just say "law is whatever the Emperor orders" and leave it at that.
That is still the central paradox of the modern world - "in the end" we may live in a Hobbesian legal environment (where the rulers can do as they wish), but it is nto a naked Hobbesian "Legal Positivism", more than lip service is paid to the idea that law is linked to REASON (not just to arbitrary will).
The reasoning of this work essentially (more than anyone else) comes from Gaius (some centuries before) who took the contending schools of Roman legal philosophy (philosophy in the general sense of reasoning) and tried to make a straightforward conclusion to them - now that the Emperor Hadrian had basically taken over the legal profession and effectively put an end to a lot of the diversity of legal thought.
But this work is not just "The Institutes of Gaius - some centuries later" it is the considered opinion of later Roman legal thinkers, on the foundation of the work of Gaius and others.
Natural law exists - but is trumped both by the law of all nations (for example all nations have slavery - so slavery being wrong does NOT mean that slavery should end), and by the will of the rulers (the will of the Emperors in this case).
And certain ways of looking at the world lead to certain conculsions (for example there is no private property in fishing rights - in the sea or in rivers), because of the way Roman philosophy (Roman reasoning) took certain principles (the Emperor did not have to rule on it - although he could .....).
There is also the basic STRUCTURE of law - law of persons, law of things...... which is familar to people today, yet comes from Roman Law.
This book is the late Roman way of looking at civil law - the rules of property, of inheritance and so on. It takes it for granted that the Emperor can change any law (that the will of the ruler trumps natural law - the exact opposite of how a scholastic in the Middle Ages would see the matter), but the work also assumes that there is a science (in the old sense of a body of knowledge - and way of reasoning) involved in law - that one can not just say "law is whatever the Emperor orders" and leave it at that.
That is still the central paradox of the modern world - "in the end" we may live in a Hobbesian legal environment (where the rulers can do as they wish), but it is nto a naked Hobbesian "Legal Positivism", more than lip service is paid to the idea that law is linked to REASON (not just to arbitrary will).
The reasoning of this work essentially (more than anyone else) comes from Gaius (some centuries before) who took the contending schools of Roman legal philosophy (philosophy in the general sense of reasoning) and tried to make a straightforward conclusion to them - now that the Emperor Hadrian had basically taken over the legal profession and effectively put an end to a lot of the diversity of legal thought.
But this work is not just "The Institutes of Gaius - some centuries later" it is the considered opinion of later Roman legal thinkers, on the foundation of the work of Gaius and others.
Natural law exists - but is trumped both by the law of all nations (for example all nations have slavery - so slavery being wrong does NOT mean that slavery should end), and by the will of the rulers (the will of the Emperors in this case).
And certain ways of looking at the world lead to certain conculsions (for example there is no private property in fishing rights - in the sea or in rivers), because of the way Roman philosophy (Roman reasoning) took certain principles (the Emperor did not have to rule on it - although he could .....).
There is also the basic STRUCTURE of law - law of persons, law of things...... which is familar to people today, yet comes from Roman Law.

blazintommyd
4.0 out of 5 stars
Well Written Introduction preferred translation
Reviewed in the United States on 17 August 2019Verified Purchase
If you're looking for the translation that most Roman Law aficionados prefer, this is it. The introduction alone is worth the price.
One person found this helpful
Report